jueves, 25 de junio de 2009

RUBEN ALMEIDA: Poda Humana y Decrecimiento Autoctono y...........


Estimados amigos: hace 250 años se inicio la era industrial y habia unos 600 millones de seres humanos en el planeta, hoy somos 6800 millones de seres humanos, son en numeros cerrados 6,000 millones de seres humanos que gracias a una actividad que tiene en peligro la vida del humano y la buena salud del planeta tierra, que se acelero la cantidad de seres humanos, hoy tenemos un promedio de vida de 74 años de vida. El planeta tierra esta vivo y algo va ser antes de que lo acabemos.
ver anexo.

Poda Humana y el Decrecimiento Autóctono

(de una noche de verano, calurosa y sofocante; indicios de que va llover)

Por Rubén Almeida

Poda Humana

Llego a mis manos la guía astrologica 2009 de Giovanna, se le considera las mas atinada por los aciertos en sus predicciones de los ultimos acontecimientos en 30 años y para este año augura terremotos y erupción de volcanes en todo el mundo y claro también en México, se considera que de este año al 2012, una baja en la población mundial del 30 al 40%.

Decrecimiento Autóctono Siempre hemos pensado que nuestros antepasados tuvieron en su desarrollo, un epoca como hoy vivimos y que dado los problemas que la sociedad presentaba decidieron llevar a cabo acciones de DECRECIMIENTO, siendo las siguientes:

Politica

Para evitar la corrupción de politicos, formaron un sistema de gobierno en base a las personas mas sabias "LOS VIEJOS" y en Consejos de ancianos se ventilaban y solucionaban todos los problemas y actividades, y no tenían sueldos (Como eran gente de probada honradez y gente de trabajo, tenían forma de vivir). Hoy en los pueblos de origen autóctono, se ven dos formas de gobierno: la autoctona manejada por Mayordomos (no cobran sueldos) y la Española, los delegados (cobran comisiones por permisos y otros).

(Los actuales polítcos de carrera, hay que temerles, son los peores).

Medio ambiente

Se quitan las grandes estucturas burocraticas Ecologicas , ya que ellos eran los que provocaban la destrucción ambiental dando los permisos e hicieron lo siguiente: Al ver que la vida se daba gracias a el Fuego, el Agua , la Tierra y el Aire los deificaron para respetarlos y los hicieron universales dandoles una conotación Espiritual, donde a cada momento de la vida de la población intervinieran, asi el fuego es la energía, la educación, la palabra etc. Y asi los demas: tierra los alimentos, el agua los sentimientos y el aire el conocimiento (hay mas pero para el caso es suficiente), si ellos eran lastimados habia penas muy severas, incluso la muerte.

Delincuencia

Se eliminan las leyes escritas y se eliminan las carceles; solo tres castigos impuestos por los cansejos de ancianos (en cada pueblo los había): La muerte, la esclavitud y el destierro. Cuando se dictaban las sentencias estaba presente el pueblo.


Eliminación del Carro

Había una gran cantidad de contaminación por tanto vehiculo y un gran crecimiento de la población, asi que el Supremo Consejo del Anahuac SCA, decide eliminar la rueda, aduciendo que el circulo es perfecto y se tiene una similitud con el Universo o sea dios. Asi logran hacer que la gente utilice mas su cuerpo y musculos y sea mas sana.

Medicina

Se eliminan las grandes sistemas del ISSTE e IMSS (algo similar) y se implanta el sistema natural de Herbolaria y sistemas terapeuticos alternativos como masajes y acupuntura con espinas de plantas como el Maguey (Agave atrovirens de las 300 especies que hay, según M. Martinez), e integran a la mujer como curandera dandole el mismo nivel que el doctor hombre. Obligando a la población a comer sano para evitar el 70% de las enfermedades, los alimentos industrializados al no consumirlos fueron desapareciendo lentamente, ademas eran mas caros que los naturales.

Basura o Residuos Sólidos Urbanos

La basura es eliminada porque al acabarse la industria que sus productos todo lo Empaca y Embala, es eliminada el 70 % de la basura, ademas se acaba la producción Agrícola de monocultivo industrial por el daño que causaba a la madre tierra y al propio humano con los pesticidas utilizados. El poder de la mercadotecnia Subliminal es eliminada por la salud mental y fisica promoviendo que las personas aprendan a pensar por si mismas y decidan comer alimentos naturales y no los industriales, que eran obligados a comer por los mensajes subliminales de las televisoras y anuncias de radio y periodicos. Con eso la prensa y medios de comunicación masivos desaparecen por inoperantes y por falsear la vida y hacerla decadente y enfermiza.

La Guerra Florida

Zas, que se dan cuenta que la naturaleza tiene un sistema que le permite evolucionar y mantenerse sana, (hoy le llaman Ecosistema), observan que en una bello conjunto de plantas de diferentes especies, a pesar de lo bello del paisaje , ellas estan pelendo a muerte, entre ellas, por el agua, el aire, la tierra y el sol; pero al mismo tiempo se respetan y forman ligas de unión muy fuertes.

Asi imponen la Guerra Florida, una guerra controlada y muy necesaria para eliminar altos jefes y población deficiente y mantener en la población un alto grado de competividad saludable. Ellos llegan a unir la Ciencia, La Religión y el arte Militar en una sola diciplina, generando dirigentes probados en los tres ordenes.

Eliminación del metal de fierro o acero

Este paso de DECRECIMIENTO fue duro y fundamental, pero un paso lleva al otro y el SCA (Supremo Consejo del Anahuac) decide que se deje de producir metales de fierro y acero, pues absorben la energía, produciendo enfermedad y su uso hacen que el humano se enloquesca de poder falso y se fabriquen maquinaria que destruyen al medio ambiente y las buenas costumbres humanas.

Eliminación de bestias de carga

Este fue un segundo paso ya que el decrecimiento fue gradual, poco a poco, ellos se prguntaban quien esta evolucionando, el animal o el humano, pues si carga el animal, es el animal el que evoluciona mas, asi que es mejor que sea el humano el que cargue.

Asi se probaba en la Nobleza autentica, un verdadero Mexicano, asi se generaban los lideres: eran Sacerdotes, eran Guerreros y eran Sabios en un solo humano.

Conocimiento profundo, el arte del Guerrero Rojo, el camino del Nahual.

Ellos comenzaban siendo analizados astrologicamente y desde su nacimiento, sabian que parte en la sociedad iban a ocupar .

Un dirigente político empezaba aprendiendo a producir alimentos, luego con el arte de la pelea cuerpo a cuerpo, luego aprendiendo el arte del acecho y el arte del ensueño, con muchas diciplinas, tenía que aprender el arte de la medicina en su propio cuerpo primero. Las practicas religiosas eran obligadas al mismo tiempo en todas sus actividades, eso hacia para someterse a diciplinas que sin esos ejercicios espirituales no lo podian lograr; luego se probaba en la guerra y si seguia vivo se iniciaba en (a los 40 a 50 años) la Recapitulación de su vida (lo primero a recapitular eran sus experiencias sexuales, es donde se gasta mas energía), asi ya podian llegar al camino de la IMPECABILIDAD, donde ya no se usa la razon y no hay dudas, pero en este punto ya no hay regreso, el guerrero ya camina junto a la muerte, hasta que llega un punto en que la desfia y el le gana.

Un guerrero no necesita historia personal, Un día descubre que ya no es necesaria y la abandona. Carlos Castaneda.

Bibliografia:

El Popol Vuh Tiene Razon, Domingo Martinez Paredez, Editorial Orión, 1976.

15 libros de Carlos Castaneda,Diana, P. Janes, Fondo de Cultura Económica, 1968, a 1999 con "El Lado Activo del Infinito" (cuando Don Juan se va y Carlos se arroja a un abismo).

Nerea (otro linaje de nahuales), Enrique Rojas Paramo, Grijalvo, 2000.

Donde Cruzan los Brujos (Historia corta de una mujer Nahual, desde su inicio hasta su final), Taisha Avelar, Diana, 1992.

América Crisol de las Razas del Mundo, Alexander von Wuthenau, Diana, 1975.

La Vida Cotidiana de los Aztecas en visperas de la Conquista, Jaques Sosutelle, Fondo de Cultura Economica, 1953.

martes, 23 de junio de 2009

¡APLICAR LA PENA DE MUERTE AL PARTIDO VERDE ECOLOGISTA DE MÉXICO! ¡Cancelar el registro del PVEM!


En 2004, a raíz del escándalo del "Niño Muerde", con relación a un soborno en Can Cun, un grupo de ambientalistas discutió la publicación de un desplegado al respecto, solicitado por "disidentes" de ese partido. En esa ocasión advertí del corrupto origen de este partido, su corrupta historia y su corrupta militancia; advertí de que no hay manera de limpiar a este partido, pues está podrido hasta el tuétano; ha sido todo lo contrario a lo que se entiende por pensamiento y acción verde ecologista en el mundo; ha sido una creación de Carlos Salinas de Gortari, Manuel Camacho Solís, Fernando Gutiérrez Barrios, el PRI, y de la Iglesia Católica Mexicana.  La legislación ambiental mexicana es un legislación "patito",  gracias también, al PVEM que ha controlado casi todas las comisiones legislativas del medio ambiente. En esa ocasión, propuse organizar la recolección de cientos de miles de firmas, para exigirle al IFE, la cancelación del registro del PVEM. 

Recientemente, el PVEM ha sido expulsado de la asociación europea de partidos verdes ecologistas, por su campaña que impulsa la pena de muerte. Se tardaron muchos años en expulsarlos, pues fueron denunciados por ecologistas y ambientalistas mexicanos ante partidos europeos hace mas de 10 años.

Ahora que el PVEM propone la pena de muerte, creo que deberíamos proponer a nuestros amigos, conocidos y vecinos la urgente aplicación de la pena de muerte al PVEM, antes de que se convierta en cómplice de secuestros y asesinatos de Estado y fomente más destrucción ecológica. 

¡APLICAR LA PENA DE MUERTE AL PARTIDO VERDE ECOLOGISTA DE MÉXICO! ¡Cancelar el registro del PVEM!

Miguel Valencia



¡Obtén la mejor experiencia en la web!
Descarga gratis el nuevo Internet Explorer 8.br> http://downloads.yahoo.com/ieak8/?l=mx

viernes, 19 de junio de 2009

GARANTIZAR QUE LA BASURA SIGA EN AUMENTO EN LA CIUDAD DE MÉXICO


El proyecto de los cinco CIRE del Gobierno del DF

Afortunadamente, se cerrará pronto el relleno sanitario del Bordo Poniente en el que se depositan diariamente 12,500 toneladas de basura; es una buena noticia saber que ningún municipio cercano al DF y ninguna demarcación periférica aceptó la creación de otro relleno sanitario para la basura del DF. Los rellenos sanitarios son una bomba ecológica de tiempo, cada día más rechazada por la sociedad mexicana. No nos hemos cansado de denunciar a los rellenos sanitarios desde hace muchos años.

En consecuencia, el gobierno del DF se ha visto obligado a encontrar una solución a este problema inmediato. Después de muchos estudios ha concluido que el concepto del CIRE, centro integral de reciclamiento y energía, con tecnología alemana, es la mejor opción en estos momentos. De acuerdo a lo que dice el Gobierno del DF, los CIRE realizan cierta separación de residuos para su reciclamiento o producción de compostas, probablemente un 25%, pero, básicamente queman la mayor parte de la basura que reciben a unos 1,300 grados centígrados, en un proceso que denominan "gasificación", el que "virtualmente no produce emisiones tóxicas" y que da como resultado energía eléctrica y arenas. Este tipo de tecnología se ha instalado, según dicen, en áreas centrales de ciertos pueblos o ciudades de Alemania. Proyecta construir cinco CIRE, el primero en Tláhuac, el segundo en Tlalpan y los demás en otros puntos de la periferia del DF, para reducir, según dice, los gastos de traslado de la basura. 

La característica central de este proyecto es que FOMENTA EL AUMENTO EN LA PRODUCCIÓN DE LA BASURA, ya que no afecta significativamente las costumbres del ciudadano, ni los costos del empresario. No tiene efectos importantes en la producción de basura, por lo que la basura puede seguir en aumento en la Ciudad de México, en los próximos años. De acuerdo con el ambientalismo en boga, la carta tecnológica ha sido colocada en la más alta prioridad, ya que se trata de interferir lo menos posible en los negocios de los responsables del crecimiento desquiciado de la basura en México: los empresarios que diseñan y producen los envases y empaques mercadotécnicos de mayor impacto en el medio ambiente y los empresarios menores ( sindicados) que controlan la recolección  y transferencia de la basura. El cambio de las costumbres del consumidor no es desde luego prioridad gubernamental. Se ignoran en este proyecto los costos de la concentración de la basura en uno o varios puntos de la ciudad, particularmente el cambio en el uso del suelo, la degradación ambiental en el área urbana seleccionada: se considera a Tlahuac como un basurero o un traspatio del DF, al que se enviarán pronto todas las actividades sucias de la ciudad: reclusorios, cuarteles, basureros, industrias, grandes unidades habitacionales, grandes bodegas, en lugar de reconocerla como lo que es: un santuario del agua, de la vida campesina y de ruinas arqueológicas. Lo que no es bueno para una comunidad o una demarcación, no es bueno para la ciudad. También se ignoran: el enorme costo que tendrá el transporte de basura en los próximos años, por el aumento brutal que se espera en los precios del petróleo y las consecuencias de la producción de basura en el cambio climático. 

La propuesta que hemos hecho por muchos años, de eliminar la recolección de basura en la Ciudad de México y de responsabilizar a cada colonia o pueblo del manejo de su basura: separar los residuos en la fuente, en el hogar; acopiarlos y tratarlos en la cercanía donde se producen: en la misma colonia, en el mismo pueblo o ejido; crear cooperativas vecinales en cada colonia que no sólo hagan estas tareas a un costo muy menor para la ciudad, también, generen mucho más empleo que cualquier megaproyecto de vialidad y transporte, como los que ahora se construyen en esta ciudad, para fomentar el uso del auto y sobre todo: REDUZCAN LA PRODUCCIÓN DE RESIDUOS O BASURA. No hay voluntad política en el Gobierno del DF, para hacer frente al problema de la basura y a los asuntos ecológicos.

¡NO A LOS CIRE!


--
Miguel Valencia
ECOMUNIDADES
Red Ecologista Autónoma de la Cuenca de México



¡Obtén la mejor experiencia en la web!
Descarga gratis el nuevo Internet Explorer 8.br> http://downloads.yahoo.com/ieak8/?l=mx

Logica Montsanto, logica de guerra


El 'mosquito' es una máquina que vuela bajo y 'riega' una nube de plaguicida. 

CHICOS ROCIADOS CON PESTICIDAS TRABAJAN COMO BANDERAS HUMANAS.

Escrito por Diario La Capital - Rosario -Argentina

 

 

'A veces me agarra dolor de cabeza en el medio del campo. Yo siempre llevo remera con cuello alto para taparme la cara y la cabeza'.
Gentileza de Arturo Avellaneda arturavellaneda@ msn.com

LOS NIÑOS FUMIGADOS DE LA SOJA

Argentina / Norte de la provincia de Santa Fe Diario La Capital

Las Petacas, Santa Fe,

29 septiembre 2006 

El viejo territorio de La Forestal , la empresa inglesa que arrasó con el quebracho colorado, embolsó millones de libras esterlinas en ganancias, convirtió bosques en desiertos, abandonó decenas de pueblos en el agujero negro de la desocupación y gozó de la complicidad de administraciones nacionales, provinciales y regionales durante más de ochenta años. 

 

Las Petacas se llama el exacto escenario del segundo estado argentino donde los pibes son usados como señales para fumigar. 

Chicos que serán rociados con herbicidas y pesticidas mientras trabajan como postes, como banderas humanas y luego serán reemplazados por otros.

'Primero se comienza a fumigar en las esquinas, lo que se llama 'esquinero'.

Después, hay que contar 24 pasos hacia un costado desde el último lugar donde pasó el 'mosquito', desde el punto del medio de la máquina y pararse allí', dice uno de los pibes entre los catorce y dieciséis años de edad.

El 'mosquito' es una máquina que vuela bajo y 'riega' una nube de plaguicida. 

Para que el conductor sepa dónde tiene que fumigar, los productores agropecuarios de la zona encontraron una solución económica: chicos de menos de 16 años, se paran con una bandera en el sitio a fumigar.. 

Los rocían con 'Randap' y a veces '2-4 D' (herbicidas usados sobre todo para cultivar soja). También tiran insecticidas y mata yuyos.

 

Tienen un olor fuertísimo.

'A veces también ayudamos a cargar el tanque. Cuando hay viento en contra nos da la nube y nos moja toda la cara', describe el niño señal, el pibe que será contaminado, el número que apenas alguien tendrá en cuenta para un módico presupuesto de inversiones en el norte santafesino.

No hay protección de ningún tipo.

Y cuando señalan el campo para que pase el mosquito cobran entre veinte y veinticinco centavos la hectárea y cincuenta centavos cuando el plaguicida se esparce desde un tractor que 'va más lerdo', dice uno de los chicos.

'Con el 'mosquito' hacen 100 o 150 hectáreas por día. Se trabaja con dos banderilleros, uno para la ida y otro para la vuelta. Trabajamos desde que sale el sol hasta la nochecita. A veces nos dan de comer ahí y otras nos traen a casa, depende del productor', agregan los entrevistados.

Uno de los chicos dice que sabe que esos líquidos le puede hacer mal: 'Que tengamos cáncer', ejemplifica. 'Hace tres o cuatro años que trabajamos en esto. En los tiempos de calor hay que aguantárselo al rayo del sol y encima el olor de ese líquido te revienta la cabeza.

A veces me agarra dolor de cabeza en el medio del campo. Yo siempre llevo remera con cuello alto para taparme la cara y la cabeza', dicen las voces de los pibes envenenados.

-Nos buscan dos productores.

Cada uno tiene su gente, pero algunos no porque usan banderillero satelital.

Hacemos un descanso al mediodía y caminamos 200 hectáreas por día.

No nos cansamos mucho porque estamos acostumbrados.

A mí me dolía la cabeza y temblaba todo. Fui al médico y me dijo que era por el trabajo que hacía, que estaba enfermo por eso', remarcan los niños.

El padre de los pibes ya no puede acompañar a sus hijos. No soporta más las hinchazones del estómago, contó. 'No tenemos otra opción. Necesitamos hacer cualquier trabajo', dice el papá cuando intenta explicar por qué sus hijos se exponen a semejante asesinato en etapas.

La Agrupación de Vecinos Autoconvocados de Las Petacas y la Fundación para la Defensa del Ambiente habían emplazado al presidente comunal Miguel Ángel Battistelli para que elabore un programa de erradicación de actividades contaminantes relacionadas con las explotaciones agropecuarias y el uso de agroquímicos.

 

No hubo avances.

Los pibes siguen de banderas.

Es en Las Petacas, norte profundo santafesino, donde todavía siguen vivas las garras de los continuadores de La Forestal.

 

Fuente: Diario La Capital , Rosario, Argentina

 

 

POR FAVOR PASALO ES IMPORTANTE QUE EL MUNDO SE ENTERE DE TODO LO QUE PASA




¡Obtén la mejor experiencia en la web!
Descarga gratis el nuevo Internet Explorer 8.br> http://downloads.yahoo.com/ieak8/?l=mx

lunes, 15 de junio de 2009

Artículo de Jean Robert: Sobre la noción de "escasez" (borrador)

Water can and ought to run freely: reflections on the notion of ‘scarcity’ in economics

Sajay Samuel & Jean Robert

[a] Introduction

The spread of commodity-intensive society has provoked a historically new feeling of perpetual lack and ineradicable dearth. By definition, commodities come at a price, which necessitates the dependence on money and muscles out self-sufficiency. The dependence on money This dependence is only deepened by the constantly stimulated desire for commodities. Not only is the capacity of self-reliance thereby frustrated and disabled, people are also incited and trained to devalue independence from commodities. Perhaps being disabled by the dependence on commodities would be acceptable were cash to grow freely on trees. But the collision between insatiable desires and a finite purse leaves the consumer in a state of perpetual dissatisfaction. Thus, commodity-intensive societies produce an incurable dis-ease: the frustration of never having enough, of feeling needy; that peculiarly modern condition of scarcity. For instance, the poor woman who cannot afford to buy bottles of the water that she once obtained freely from a tap or a well experiences scarcity as does the rich man who cannot quench his thirst with Aquafina after becoming aware of Perrier. Both are equally dependent on market values. Yet he, being enslaved to commodities, has forgotten what she still acutely remembers: the propriety of using water that can and ought to run freely.1

Scarcity means ‘the insufficiency of supply; smallness of available quantity, number or amount, in proportion to need or demand’ (OED, emphasis added). As such, scarcity is a relational term. While the quantity of a thing is a necessary condition, excessive desire or demand is a sufficient condition for the experience of scarcity. The overflowing shelves and garbage heaps of commodity-intensive society are proof of the abundance of things. And, as scientists inform us, the total quantity of the stuff named H20 remains unchanged through the hydrological cycle, neither created nor destroyed. Yet, the perception of endemic scarcity intensifies in commodity-intensive society. This, we argue, is primarily due to the limitless desire for accumulation sparked and fed by the ideological commitments of the mainstream of economic science.

In this paper, we first contrast Aristotle with Adam Smith to bring this ideological ground into sharp relief. As our contrastive reading of shows, Smith centres the study of political economy on exchange value. In doing so, he overturns the traditional understanding of ‘economics’ in two ways: he excises use-value from its purview and also legitimises vanity and greed. He understands and accepts that these vices drive the accumulation of wealth beyond use. Nevertheless, he masks their viciousness under the benign phrase ‘bettering our condition.’ In justifying limitless acquisitiveness or accumulation beyond use, mainstream economic thought produces scarcity. Second, we show that neo-classical economics no less than the classical economics of Adam Smith actively hides its acquisitive foundations to make it palatable. The utility theory of neo-classical economics hides the assumption of ‘more is better’ under mathematical robes. In both cases, unfettered desire or demand is taken-for-granted and fuels the spread of ineradicable scarcity. Third, though the spread of economic thought styles also spreads the ideology of more is better, we point out that the mathematical commitments of neo-classical economics requires it to be styled as a ‘science of scarcity’ in which scarcity is posited as quantitative constraints of athe limited quantity of time, means or money. By confusing finiteness (a question of quantities) with scarcity, mainstream economic science is blind to the fact that it helps produce the very problem it purports to solve. By now, ironically,

Yet, it is economic notions of demand, supply, production, consumption, allocation, distribution, and prices that suffuses the discourse on ‘water scarcity.’ The hegemony of economic terms reinforces the notion that water is a resource. Instead, as we argue in the conclusion to this paper, the urgent task in adequately grasping the question of scarcity in the context of water is to see first that water is a commons.

[a] From the Good to Values

For over two thousand years, ‘economics’ was a branch of politics or moral philosophy. From Xenophon’s Oikonomikos in the fourth century B.C., to Adam Smith’s teacher, Francis Hutchinson’s Short introduction to Moral Philosophy in 1742, oeconomics referred to the ethical art of running a household: of how to deal with food stores, the training towards virtue of women, children and servants. (Finley, 1985, pp17-21).2 What are now accepted as the subjects of economic science – trade and exchange, money, distribution and so on – traditionally belonged to the study of politics, understood as reflections on the highest good for man. To buttress this point, it is perhaps sufficient to note that all of Aristotle’s writings on ‘economics’ appear either in the Ethics or the Politics. The first lines of these works reveal the traditionally understood end of ethics and politics and a fortiori, the proper end of ‘economic’ matters.3 In the Aristotelian tradition that infused Western thinking on ‘economics’ until the early modern period, trade, barter and exchange are species of human activities practised within polities. Since both human actions and political arrangements strain naturally towards the good, ‘economic’ affairs are necessarily subject to considerations of the good.

Aristotle’s discussion of the arts of acquisition provides a clear explanation for why exchange relations ought to be subjected to ethics and politics. In his Politics, he distinguishes two kinds of acquisitive arts. The first is the art of acquisition oriented by natural needs and therefore a proper part of household management; oikonomia.4 The second, called ‘the art of wealth-getting’ or chrematistics, is exemplified by ‘retail trade.’ Retail trade or buying goods for the purpose of reselling them at a profit produces wealth solely through exchange.

Aristotle argued that activities ordered by profit-seeking were unfitting and unnatural because animated by the purpose of accumulating money for itself. Accordingly to Aristotle, wealth-getting is perverse in two ways. First, the heterogeneity of human actions and of things is effaced when subjected to the reign of exchange. When purchased for the purpose of resale, a shoe is not qualitatively different from a table; both are rendered into commodities. Commodities subsume and bury that heterogeneity of things which is partly conferred by the distinct uses to which they are put. Similarly, as paid services, cooking is equated to gardening, both rendered homogenous as undifferentiated forms of ‘labour,’ which effaces the meaningfulness of human actions.5

Second and equally important Besides, for Aristotle, was the fact that the accumulation of money for itself is unchained from natural ends – those of needs or use. When purchased for resale, no quantity of shoes is enough. Shoes then become a cipher for money whose accumulation has no inherent end or principle of self-limitation. Unhinged from natural needs or use, accumulation leads to the fate of Midas – who starved to death while sitting on a hoard of coins. Therefore, for Aristotle, to live by exchange exhibits a derangement of reason: the retailer unreasonably forgets the distinction between merely living and living well.6 Politics and ethics were oriented by the good and implied reflections on the good life. The art of wealth-getting which aims at profit making, because inherently limitless, is destructive of ethics and politics. It is precisely for this reason that Aristotle censures getting wealth through exchange.

In his Inquiry into The Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, Adam Smith turned the Aristotelian tradition on its head. Instead of grounding his inquiry on the questions of the good and the just, he legitimizeds the art of wealth-getting. It is this overturning that constitutes his lasting bequest to modern economics. To properly grasp his innovation therefore, one should begin by considering the stated purpose for undertaking the inquiry.

Smith defines ‘political economy’ as a science exclusively directed by two ends: to enable individuals and the state to acquire wealth.7 He thus legitimizes the acquisition of wealth and thereby frees acquisitiveness from ethico-political restraints. Despite the arrangement of words in Smith’s ‘political economy’, the principle of commercialism is not subservient in rank to that of politics. Instead, justice is reduced in status to a handmaiden of wealth-getting. The witness of Andrew Millar, an auditor of Smith’s lectures on jurisprudence is instructive in this regard.

“In the last part of his lectures he [Smith] examined those political regulations which are founded not upon the principle of justice, but that of expediency, and which are calculated to increase the riches, the power and the prosperity of a state … What he delivered on these subjects contained the substance of the work he afterwards published under the title of An Inquiry into the Nature and causes of the Wealth of Nations.” (cited in Cannan, 1904).

By placing economic science in the service of accumulating wealth, Smith stakes out its purpose. It is to achieve this end that he also restricts its subject matter to the determinants of market prices; to the sphere of exchange-value. He accepted Locke’s arguments: that labour is the foundation of property rights; that applying labour transforms the commons into private property; that money ignites the spirit of acquisitiveness; and that accumulation beyond use is just.8 Smith curtails his inquiry to exchange-value in full awareness of the contrasting ‘value-in-use’ and is perhaps the first who, in recognizing that traditional distinction, nevertheless rules out use-value as a legitimate subject of an inquiry on wealth.9

In this context, consider the distinction Smith draws between diamonds and water. He recognizes that water is useful but of little value in exchange, whereas diamonds are almost useless but nevertheless expensive (Smith 1895, Bk 1, Ch.2). Well before him, it was known that the most useful stuff for life is free and that superfluities could be expensive. I n the XVIIth century, for instance, Pufendorf still could write: “… those things are of the least account of Value without which Human Life is least able to subsist; and therefore not without the most singular Providence of Almighty God, Nature has been very bountiful in providing a plentiful store of those things. But the wanton Luxury of Mankind has set extravagant Rates upon many things which Humane life might very well be without, for instance upon Pearls and Jewels.” (Samuel Pufendorf, in Kauder, 1953, p650).

In contrast, However, Smith does not follow this Aristotelian tradition in evaluating the propriety of value-in-exchange by value-in-use. He can therefore eschews any ethical or moral judgment on the sphere of exchange-values, and instead focus the study of political economy on the sphere of the useless. Smith He could so “ignore” use-value by naturalizing perversity, that is, by ennobling the quest for wealth. He disavowed the Aristotelian ethico-political restrictions on exchange by explicitly enjoining men and states to acquire riches. For Aristotle, the retailer exhibits a derangement of reason. For Smith, every man is reasonable insofar as he lives as a retailer.10 For Aristotle, the retailer’s deranged acquisitiveness was unnatural because it suppressed or perverted his natural sociability. For Smith, man’s sociability was the outcome of his selfishness or self-interest, expressed in the natural propensity to truck, barter and exchange.11

And yet, though Smith recognized that the causes of wealth were rooted in unseemly passions or vices, he was chary to call them as such. Indeed, his earlier reflections on the moral sentiments can be read as an attempt to rhetorically remove the sting of viciousness from vice. Smith recognized the a recognition that ‘avarice and ambition’ attended the endless ‘pursuit of wealth, power and pre-eminence’ as he did the ‘emulation which runs through all the different ranks of men.’ .He emphasized it was vanity, rooted in ‘the belief of our being the object of attention’ and ‘not the ease or the pleasure’ that drove men to ‘pursue riches and avoid poverty.’ (Smith, 1858, Part 8, Sec 2, Ch.3).

But, as he argued, ‘virtue consists not in any one affection but in the proper degree of all the affections’ and it is ‘sympathy’ or the ‘correspondent affection of the spectator’ that ‘is the natural and original measure of the proper degree [of virtue]’ (Smith, 1858, ibid). Yet in Smith, ‘sympathy’ is a neutral scientific term that cannot discriminate between good and bad.12 It is better understood as a physiological reaction to the dominant social prejudice of market societies. For Smith, men sympathize with those who ‘make a parade of their riches’. And men parade their riches to provoke the sympathy of others. Mutual sympathy is the glue bonding men to that ceaseless ‘toil and bustle’ necessary to acquire more than they need. Therefore, ‘sympathy’ is neither the compassion felt for the poor and downtrodden nor the fellow-feeling towards the sick and distressed. Instead, in Smith, ‘sympathy’ is the reward for vanity. in commercial society where unlimited acquisitiveness is the dominating value.

And if ‘sympathy’ was not neutral enough, Smith also introduces the more benign phrase ‘bettering our condition’ to better justify and legitimize the vainglorious pursuit of wealth.13 The continued importance of this phrase is underscored by the fact that it is as recognizable and acceptable today as when he first advanced it. For who now would deny the benign effort to ‘better one’s condition’? He argued that the desire to better our condition ‘comes with us from the womb and never leaves us till we go to the grave’ and that it excites a ‘uniform, constant and uninterrupted effort’ towards wealth-getting that fuels both public and private opulence.14 Thus, Smith legitimizes acquisitiveness by rephrasing it as a natural desire to better our condition, laying .

Thus Smith lays the ideological scaffolding for modern economics. By making plausible exchange for the purpose of accumulation as the inevitable outcome of the natural propensity to truck and barter and towards sympathy, Smith clears the grounds for justifying commodity-intensive market society. By transforming the vice of vanity and envy into the natural desire to better our condition, he makes the causes of wealth palatable. He thus displaces the traditional reflections on ‘economics’ which began from considerations of the good. No pre-modern could think to hold in esteem that which was not estimable. Neither Aristotle nor the scholastics could conceive the accumulation of wealth for itself as good. Instead, Smith extricated ‘economics’ from its traditional moorings in ethics and politics to better accept the purpose of political economy as the accumulation of wealth. Yet, this also legitimizes the sufficient condition for scarcity, the limitless desire for acquisitions that exceeds both need and use.15

[a]Utility is not useful

Despite the many differences between classical and neo-classical economics, they share a common ideological ground. In this mainstream of economic science, use-value is ignored and unfettered acquisitiveness ennobled. Whereas Smith used the phrase ‘bettering our condition’ to mask and make palatable the ignoble causes of wealth, neo-classical economics achieves the same result through its notion of utility. Utility is assumed to increase with the more one possesses, so that 3 chairs and 3 tables offer greater utility than 2 of each. The assumption that ‘more is better’ therefore throws mathematical clothes over the skeleton of unfettered desire.

Popularly enshrined as marking the ‘marginal revolution’ in economic thought, neoclassical economics is now considered the new and improved version of economic science. Broadly, the marginal revolution consisted of the discovery that the intensity of the desire for a thing determined, in fine, its value-in-exchange. The novelty of the utility theory of value supposedly lies in replacing the objective quantity of labour time with the purely subjective feeling of desire as the ground of exchange value. Yet, inadequacy of this interpretation is proved by the fact that classical economists had already accepted the need or desire for a thing as a necessary though not sufficient condition of its exchange-value.16 Moreover, as Marx noted, “usefulness does not dangle midair…it is conditioned by the physical properties of the commodity…” (1954).

What is decisively new in neoclassical economics is that ‘utility’ becomes a place-holder for a mathematical construct.17 Already, in Bentham, utility had become the subject matter of an abstract principle subtending a ‘felicific calculus’. His ‘principle of utility’ allowed the calibration of individual pleasures and pains and the purported calculation of the greatest happiness for the greatest number. Benthamite utilitarianism can see no difference between the usefulness of human remains to a vulture and its utility to an organ-harvesting company. Yet, it is no mere Benthamite abstraction that is affirmed by the marginal revolution in economics. Instead, when for example, Jevons asserts ‘value depends entirely on utility’, he reinterprets everyday experience and language to suit a mathematical function. It is well known that the invention of ‘diminishing marginal utility’ constitutes the real and lasting novelty of neoclassical economics, obtained by fitting economic thought to the structure of differential calculus. If a differentiable function is named ‘utility’ and its first derivative ‘marginal utility,’ then the quasi-concavity of that function is sufficient to establish ‘diminishing marginal utility’. Jevons is a good witness to the convolutions required in retrofitting ordinary experience to suit mathematical functions. He refers to water as an example to lend everyday credibility to his formulations but then strains ordinary credulity by suggesting that men drink water to the point of being sickened by it.18

Despite its overt mathematization, neo-classical economics shares the ideological conceit of unlimited acquisitiveness bequeathed to it by classical economics. Perhaps Marshalls states the proposition most succinctly, “There is an endless variety of wants, but there is a limit to each separate want” (Marshall, 1890, p155). Whereas the second part of the proposition reflects the innovation of diminishing marginal utility, the first recognizes vanity as the wellspring of commodity-intensive society. The assumption of limitless wants is axiomatic in neo-classical economics, and usually ascribed to ‘tastes and preferences’ beyond the scope of economic analysis. Thus, it assumes acquisitiveness is an ineradicable aspect of human nature instead of a socially conditioned behaviour. The techniques of utility maximization and the geometry of indifference maps obscures the fact that neo-classical economics takes as its foundational assumption the very behaviour or attitude that produces the experience of scarcity. Regardless of quantities or availability, unbounded desire will necessarily create scarcity, and this dynamic is buried at the heart of mainstream economic thought.

Smith placed use-value in the blind spot of economics though he recognized usefulness as the first meaning of ‘value.’ Neoclassical economists identified ‘value’ with what was obtained in exchange and could no longer comprehend usefulness. Blind to what Smith had blinkered beyond economics, neoclassical economists could not imagine alternatives to market society.19 However, by legitimizing unfettered acquisitiveness prompted by vanity, whether through such rhetorical flourishes as ‘bettering our condition’ or mathematical obscurities as ‘utility’ and ‘indifference maps’, the mainstream of economic science propagates the sufficient condition of scarcity.

[a]Scarcity is not finiteness

Yet, the notion of scarcity as a universal and ineradicable condition was given scientific credence by XXth century economists. ‘Scarcity’, like ‘utility’, is a word deployed to make mathematical economics ordinarily comprehensible. Léon Walras was perhaps the most active in transferring the mathematics of energy physics to economics. Unsurprisingly, it is also he who most clearly formulated ‘scarcity’ as the indispensable source of economic value.20 Yet, the idea that scarcity defines ‘the raison d’être of economic science’ was not widely accepted until the 1930s, which is when mathematical formulations become central to it.21 As an endemic human condition justifying economics, scarcity usually shows up only in the popularization of economics in trade and text books. Indeed, it would not be a great exaggeration to suggest that it was Lionel Robbins who gave wide currency to the notion of ‘economics as a science of scarcity’ (See Fine, Toye and Luks, this volume, for further discussions of Robbins’ notion of economics and scarcity).22

The mathematics of constrained optimization is the kernel of XXth century economic theorizing.23 Consumers are said to maximize their utility subject to the constraint of income, producers are said to maximize their output given the quantity of capital and labour available, as Robinson Crusoe allocates his labour among tasks given the constraint of time. Without constraints, whether of time, money, or means, there is no economic problem. It is in the context of the mathematical technique of constrained maximization then, that ‘scarcity’ in economics must be understood. Specifically, ‘scarcity’ is to constraints as ‘marginal utility’ is to a differentiable and quasi-concave function. Modern economists rarely consider ‘scarcity’ a technical term and unlike ‘balance of payments’, or ‘n-person games’, scarcity does not usually appear in technical treatises on economics.24 @ Scarcity however is rhetorically convenient for popularizing economic science. It fuels that perception that economics deals with problems necessitated by the limited quantity of means, or money, or time (See Fine, this volume, for a discussion on the elusive nature of scarcity in economics.)

In contrast, when classical economists spoke of ‘scarcity’ they typically meant ‘rare,’ ‘little’ or ‘infrequent’ (see also Xenos, this volume). They did not imagine any scarcity in the case of producible goods. Ricardo’s reasoning seems persuasive: in distinguishing between two kinds of price, he notes that the ‘scarcity price’ is independent of the quantity of labour. Instead, such prices are applicable only to rare objects that are necessarily limited in number. The prices of such rarities are therefore determined by the competing desires of those who wanted to possess them. To the classical economist however, this ‘scarcity price’ was an exceptional phenomenon in the sphere of exchange and could not be used to explain the value of what was abundant. After all, the glut in manufactured goods was self-evident to them.25

Scarcity is an inherently relational concept. It refers to the dearth, the insufficiency of something; that is, the quantity of something in relation to the need, want or desire for it. Scarcity should be distinguished from finiteness, which is not a relational concept. Finiteness is an objective property of things independent of the needs or purposes of men. Obviously, finite quantities do not imply fixed quantities – the quantity of rainwater in the Sahel may vary from year to year but in each year there is a finite amount. In contrast, whether a finite quantity of water is insufficient depends on the purposes of its use. The amount that is excessive for a home with a dry toilet will be insufficient for one with five flush toilets and a lawn. Thus insufficiency or scarcity necessarily entails judgments on the appropriateness of needs and wants. Evaluations of scarcity or abundance, of too little or too much, are non-quantifiable judgments utterly distinct from numerical measurements.26

This contrast between finiteness and scarcity is not sufficiently drawn either in economics or more generally.27 Scarcity is a relational measure of experience, inextricably binding the quantity of things to the purposes of men. It is a measure of the insufficiency of finite quantities and cannot itself be measured by number. In contrast, the finiteness of a thing can be measured in numbers. For example, ‘X gallons’ is a quantitative measure of the finiteness or limitedness of water. Scarcity cannot be reduced to finiteness since finiteness is only a necessary but not sufficient condition of scarcity. That water is finite is a truism that does not imply that water is scarce. Despite the conceptual distinction between finiteness and scarcity, the latter has a strange connotative power. Typically, the phrase ‘X is scarce’ draws attention to the quantity of X while passing over the purposes for which it is insufficient. The phrase ‘water is scarce’ tends to mistakenly emphasize only the necessary but not sufficient condition that makes water scarce; it tends to reduce the experience of scarcity to the quantity of water.

Neoclassical economists are heirs to the classical economists insofar as they accept acquisitiveness as a natural condition. To popularize constrained maximization as the ‘science of scarcity’, they however foster a systematic confusion between finiteness and scarcity. The ‘scarcity’ they invoke is endemic and ineradicable. It is not caused by the unavailability of things. After all, the landfills that have grown to the size of small hills are enough proof that modern societies waste more than previous generations have ever consumed or used. Instead, scarcity is now inexpungible because needs have proliferated into endless wants. Yet the tendency of ‘scarcity’ to be identified with limited quantities suggests otherwise. Perhaps the connotative power of ‘scarcity’ is a leftover from bygone days when needs were culturally bound and stable. Perhaps it is now actively maintained to prevent judgement on the appropriateness of wants and desires. In either case, the use of ‘scarcity’ today tends to reinforce the illusion that it is caused by the unavailability of things instead of the excessiveness of wants. And it is the mainstream of economic science since Adam Smith that has signally contributed to this illusion. On the one hand it legitimizes and propagates the sufficient condition of the experience of scarcity—insatiable desires; and on the other, proposes to solve the problems created by such limitless acquisitiveness.

Water is a commons

This dual dynamic of attempting to solve a problem with the same thought style that contributes to it, is painfully obvious in the case of the growing concern with ‘water scarcity.’ In the context of this discourse, water is considered a resource. Caught in the conceptual web of demand and supply, policymakers can only think of ways to increase the quantity or decrease the consumption of water resources. And, unsurprisingly, they focus on the price mechanism as a panacea. They want to price water so that the gifts of nature can be converted into private property. They want to price water to spur increases in supply by, for example, turning seawater into fresh water. They want to price water to restrict the effective demand for it. They propagate the reign of prices to transmute the needs of all into the wants of the few who can pay.28 In their rush to find efficient solutions to the problem of water scarcity, they have conveniently forgotten that commodities necessarily introduce scarcity into market society. For where cash is king, self-sufficiency and the commons are cast into exile. Under the rule of prices, the abundant can also be unaffordable. Moreover, prices may reduce the effective demand for Perrier and flush toilets but can also spark the envious desire for them it.29 Unlike their predecessors, modern economists who propagate the price mechanism forget what Adam Smith knew: that vanity fuels the engine of commercial society.

That the unfettered spread of commodity-intensive society has led to the despoliation of the air, soil and water is obvious enough. That commodity-intensive society has produced a cornucopia of things the majority cannot afford is equally obvious. However, that commodity-intensive society induces scarcity by fuelling acquisitiveness is not sufficiently obvious. From its inception, economics has been chained to the ball of market exchange. Its proponents can only tout more markets as solutions to the very problems created by market society, that is, to create more scarcity pretending in order to eradicate scarcity.

The question of scarcity today cannot be divorced from the question of the needs and wants of man. Addressing the question of needs and wants is pre-eminently a process of judging when something is too much or too little; of judging if and when needless wants have replaced useful needs. Is industrial farming counter-productive? Do dams damage? Are flush toilets and green lawns necessary? Are desalination technologies appropriate? These are questions of ethics and politics. They cannot be comprehended in the terms of an economic science, which was consciously established beyond ethics and politics. Blind to use-values while celebrating acquisitiveness, mainstream economics is of little help in thinking about the proposition that ‘water is scarce’. What it pretends to solve with one hand, it contributes to with the other. A discourse based on thinking about water as a resource, caught within the conceptual pincers of demand and supply, rife with ‘allocation’, ‘distribution’, ‘production’ and ‘consumption’ only obfuscates the modern experience of scarcity.

A way out of the mental prison of water as a resource is to recall that water was, until very recently, a commons. The contrast between water as a commons and as a resource was well exposed over the turn of the XIXth century. Aqua currit et debet currere; ‘water runs and ought to run’ ruled the judge in the Merritt v Parker case (1795, New Jersey). He thus recalled that well-worn maxim of common law which prohibited interference to water-course flows. As William Blackstone noted, “water is a moving, wandering think thing, and must of necessity continue to be common by the law of nature so I can only have a temporary, transient, usufructuary property therein”(cited in Shiva, 2002, p. 20). Historically, diverting or significantly obstructing the natural course of water was always judged illegal unless agreed to by all parties affected. Yet, a scarce hardly ten years later, the judges in the case of Palmer v Mulligan (1805, New York) ruled legitimate the damming of water for the purpose of a mill. The difference between the two rulings defined the XIXth century transformation in the legal conception of property. Law would no longer protect the liberty to the quiet enjoyment of property that was once honoured by the common law maxim sic utere tuo, ut alienum non laedas, “so use yours that others be not harmed”. Instead, the liberty to quiet and harmless enjoyment was legally destroyed when the rights of ownership were recast to permit the commercial development of property, even if to the detriment of another’s use. To legalize economic growth and commodity-intensive society, judges began to use a brand new economic and utilitarian criterion to assess legal damages: the economic efficiency gained from restricting liberty. Accordingly, the commons could be exploited for private commercial purposes as long as the cash value to the one owner outweighed the loss of another’s liberty. Law was thus wielded as an instrument of commercialism to separate what was kept together by common law for centuries: the coincidence of injurious misuse and legally determined damages. It did so by comparing what could only be contrasted: legal rights and civil liberties. Instrumental law not only defanged neighbourly conflict by reducing politics to the economic calculus of cost and benefit but also legally transformed water into a privately exploitable resource. Indeed, as Horowitz (1977) argues, economic growth in the US during the first half of the XIXth century went hand in hand with privatizing the water commons.30

To see water as a commons, again, requires attending to those who, like contemporaries in the Thar desert of Rajasthan, live well without imagining that water is scarce (Shiva 2002). It requires being free of the debilitating effects of attached to economic styles of thinking. capable of producing sentences such as this ‘…and there were some mystical references to the infinite utility of subsistence’ (1950, p373). It calls for a revaluation of self-sufficiency and of living within natural thresholds, which for the Nobel Laureate, Herbert Simon, occurs only in fast-disappearing black zones of ‘autarky’ (1991, pp25–44).

[a]Notes

1 The literature on the contrast between commodity-intensive society and its antithesis is extensive. For an orientation to this contrast that admits no synthesis, consult Illich, 1980. He rehabilitates the word ‘vernacular’ to indicate social arrangements, past and present, wherein the ‘the home-grown, home-bred and home-spun’ dominate the dependence on purchased goods and services. William Leiss (1988) coined the phrase ‘high-intensity market setting’ to refer to ‘a market economy in which there is a very large number of commodities available to a large number of people, and in which many commodities are the result of highly complex industrial production processes involving sophisticated scientific and technological knowledge’ (p7). The works of Karl Polanyi, (1944; Polanyi et al, 1957; Dalton, 1968) clarify the historicity of commodity-intensive societies, made visible when nature and human action become widely priced as land and labour respectively. Marshall Sahlins (1972) and Finley (1985) confirm that pre-modern societies, whether Aboriginal Australia or Western Antiquity, got on quite well without it. Jacques Le Goff (1988) emphasizes the aim of the medieval ‘economy’ as that of subsistence, of providing for necessities. The continuing modern war on subsistence and the resistance to it is well documented. Consult for example, Thompson, 2000; Wolf, 1977; Shanin, 1977; and Marcos, 2001). Scott (1999) argues that visionary plans to modernize society invariably fail and usually leave their beneficiaries worse off for the attention. Study the key terms collected in Sachs (1992) as commands that rally the troops to the war against subsistence.

2 When Adam Smith wrote The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1858) some 17 years before publishing An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, (1875) he still adhered to this traditional meaning of oeconomics.

3 The first sentence of the Nicomachean Ethics reads ‘Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and choice, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim’ (Bk.1, 1094a1). Similarly, the first sentence of The Politics reads ‘Every state is a community of some kind, and every community is established with a view to some good; …[and] the state…aims…at the highest good’ (Bk.1, 1252a1).

4 ‘Of the art of acquisition then there is one kind which by nature is a part of the management of a household, in so far as the art of household management must either find ready to hand, or itself provide, such things necessary to life, and useful for the community of the family or the state, as can be stored. They are the elements of true riches; for the amount of property which is needed for a good life is not unlimited …’ (Aristotle, Politics, Bk.1, Ch.8, 1256b).

5 The Nichomacean Ethics contains Aristotle’s discussion on the (in)appropriateness of the commensurability entailed by exchange. See Scott Meikle (1995) for an outstanding treatment of the (un)resolved problem of commensurability that haunts modern economics. Hannah Arendt (1958) finely crafts the distinctions between ‘work’, ‘labour’ and ‘action.’

6 ‘The origin of this disposition (accumulation of coin for itself) in men is that they are intent upon living only, and not upon living well; and as their desires are unlimited, they also desire that the means of gratifying them should be without limit. … [Thus] some men turn every quality or art into a means of getting wealth; this they conceive to be the end, and to the promotion of the end they think all things must contribute’ (Aristotle, Politics, Bk.1, Ch.9, 1258a). ‘There are two sorts of wealth-getting, as I have said; one is a part of household management, the other is retail trade: the former necessary and honorable, while that which consists in exchange is justly censured; for it is unnatural, and a mode by which men gain from one another’ (Aristotle, Politics, Bk.1, Ch.10, 1258a & b).

7 “Political economy … proposes two distinct objects: first, to … enable [people] to provide a (plentiful) revenue or subsistence for themselves, and secondly, to supply the state or commonwealth with a revenue sufficient for the public services.” Though ‘political economy, [is] considered as a branch of the science of a statesman or legislator …its stated purpose is ‘to enrich both the people and the sovereign” (Smith, 1875, Bk.4, Introduction). The phrase ‘political economy’ was used by James Steuart Denham (1712-1780) in An Inquiry into the Principles of Political Economy (1767) but there refers to the paternalistic task of a prince. In its Smithian sense, the locution will run through Ricardo, Mill, and Jevons until Marshalls’s Principles of Economics first published in 1890. There Marshall contracts ‘political economy’ to ‘economics’ and he defines it on the ground laid by Smith. Thus, “Political Economy or Economics is a study of mankind in the ordinary business of life; it examines that part of individual and social action which is most closely connected with the attainment and with the use of the material requisites of wellbeing.”

8 The importance of Locke to Smith is evident in his paean to property. “The property which every man has in his own labour, as it is the original foundation of all other property, so it is the most sacred and inviolable”, (Smith, 1875, Bk.1, Ch.10, Pt.2). For reasons of space, we do not offer detailed quotations from Locke to support our argument of Smith’s dependence on him. However, see John Locke, Concerning Civil Government, second Essay, Ch. 5.

9 “… money has become in all civilized nations the universal instrument of commerce, by the intervention of which goods of all kinds are bought and sold, or exchanged for one another. What are the rules which men naturally observe in exchanging them either for money or one another, I shall now proceed to examine. These rules determine what may be called the relative or exchangeable value of goods.” “…The word value, it is to be observed, has two different meanings, and sometimes expresses the utility of some particular object, and sometimes the power of purchasing other goods which the possession of that object conveys. The one may be called ‘value in use’; the other, ‘value in exchange’ ” (Smith, 1875, Bk.1, Ch.4).

10 A man “supplies the far greater part of them (his wants) by exchanging that surplus part of the produce of his own labor, which is over and above his own consumption, for such parts of the produce of other men’s labor as he has occasion for. Every man thus lives by exchanging, or becomes in some measure a merchant, and the society itself grows to be what is properly a commercial society.” (Smith, 1875, Bk.1, Ch.4)

11 Thus, “we are not ready to suspect any person of being defective in selfishness” (Smith, 1858, Pt.8, Sec.2, Ch.3). “This division of labor, from which so many advantages are derived, is not originally the effect of any human wisdom, which foresees and intends that general opulence to which it gives occasion. It is the necessary, though very slow and gradual consequence of a certain propensity in human nature which has in view no such extensive utility; the propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another.” (Smith, 1875, Bk.1, Ch.2).

12 We are aware of the ‘Adam Smith Problem,’ usefully summarized by Leonidas Montes (2003, pp63–90). ‘The Problem as such, states that there is an irreconcilable difference or inconsistency between The Theory of Moral Sentiments, with its sympathy-based concept of human nature, and The Wealth of Nations, founded on an egoistic theory of self-interest’ (p66). We contend that since Smith’s ‘sympathy’ is evoked by the envious and the vain, the ‘Das Adam Smith Problem’ is not Adam Smith’s problem.

13 “It is because mankind are disposed to sympathize more entirely with our joy than with our sorrow, that we make parade of our riches, and conceal our poverty … Nay, it is chiefly from this regard to the sentiments of mankind, that we pursue riches and avoid poverty. For to what purpose is all the toil and bustle of this world? What is the end of avarice and ambition, of the pursuit of wealth, of power, and preheminence? Is it to supply the necessities of nature? The wages of the meanest labourer can supply them … If we examined his oeconomy with rigour, we should find that he spends a great part of them upon conveniencies, which may be regarded as superfluities, and that, upon extraordinary occasions, he can give something even to vanity and distinction … From whence, then, arises that emulation which runs through all the different ranks of men, and what are the advantages which we propose by that great purpose of human life which we call bettering our condition? To be observed, to be attended to, to be taken notice of with sympathy, complacency, and approbation, are all the advantages which we can propose to derive from it. It is the vanity, not the ease, or the pleasure, which interests us. But vanity is always founded upon the belief of our being the object of attention and approbation.” (Smith, 1858, Pt.1, Sec.1, Ch.3, [emphasis added].

14 See his discussion on ‘bettering our condition’ in Smith, 1875, Bk.2, Ch.3. Here, in The Wealth of Nations he assumes what he argued for in Moral Sentiments: that avarice, ambition, and vanity can be reduced to ‘bettering our condition’.

15 How mimetic desire becomes acceptable because it is functional for commercial society can be read in the writings of Hobbes, Locke, Hume, Mandeville and Rousseau up to the classical economists. Desire is endlessly stoked and never satisfied when ‘I want what you have’. From Mandeville to Keynes the perception that vice produces wealth depends on seeing that desire unhinged from use – acquisitiveness – can never be satisfied. Social scientists lack such perception. For scarcity as rooted in mimetic desire consult Girard, 1976; Dumochel and Dupuy, 1979; Nicholas Xenos, 1989; Hans Achterhuis, 1993; Mandeville, 1924; Keynes, 1972.

16. David Ricardo clearly states the role of utility in classical economics. “Utility then is not the measure of exchangeable value, although it is absolutely essential to it. If a commodity were in no way useful – in other words, if it could in no way contribute to our gratification – it would be destitute of exchangeable value, however scarce it might be, or whatever quantity of labour might be necessary to procure it” in Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, 1817, Ch.1, Sec.1.

17 See Philip Mirowski, 1989, and its useful summary in Mirowski 1988, where he writes, “It is the second thesis of this paper that the hard core of neoclassical economic theory is the adoption of mid-nineteenth century physics as a rigid paradigm … [which] … explains the preference for techniques of constrained maximization over any other analytical technique.” (p24). More generally, he offers compelling evidence for the argument that ‘utility’ in neoclassical economics was identified with ‘potential energy’ in XIXth century physics. He emphasizes the futility of this attempted identification by noting that it is meaningless to speak of the sum of income and utility being conserved through market exchanges, as does the sum of kinetic and potential energy when a ball falls to the ground.

18 “Water, for instance, may be roughly described as the most useful of all substances. A quart of water per day has the high utility of saving a person from dying in a most distressing manner. Several gallons a day may possess much utility for such purposes as cooking and washing; but after an adequate supply is secured for these uses, any additional quantity is a matter of comparative indifference. All that we can say, then, is, that water, up to a certain quantity, is indispensable; that further quantities will have various degrees of utility; but that beyond a certain quantity the utility sinks gradually to zero; it may even become negative, that is to say, further supplies of the same substance may become inconvenient and hurtful’ (Jevons, 1988, Ch.3).

19 By the end of the XIXth century, value-in-use lost all meaning as noted by Alfred Marshall. “The word ‘value’ ”, says Adam Smith, “has two different meanings, and sometimes expresses the utility of some particular object and sometimes the power of purchasing other goods which the possession of that object conveys.” But experience has shown that it is not well to use the word in the former sense. The value, that is the exchange value, of one thing in terms of another at any place and time, is the amount of that second thing which can be got there and then in exchange for the first. Thus the term value is relative, and expresses the relation between two things at a particular place and time’ (Marshall, 1898, Bk.II, Ch.II).

20 The term or concept does not appear of any importance in Jevons or Marshall. Menger has the concept without the word. It was Léon Walras, perhaps the most mathematical of XIXth century economists, who is the outstanding exception. “Whether labour is all or part of social wealth is beside the point. In either case, why is labour worth anything? Why is it exchangeable? That is the question before us. Adam Smith neither asked nor answered it. Surely, if labour has value and is exchangeable, it is because it is both useful and limited in quantity, that is to say because it is scarce. Value therefore comes from scarcity. If there are things other than labour that are scarce, they will also have value and be exchangeable. So the theory which traces the origin of value to labour is a theory that is completely devoid of meaning rather than too narrow, entirely gratuitous rather than merely deficient.” (in Jolink, 1996) [emphasis added].

21 see Pearce, 1986, p379. The thorough-going mathematization of economic science is a XXth century phenomenon and tracks the spread of marginalism in economics. “In the 1930’s new uses for the marginal concept were introduced in the journals and the specialized literature.” (Howey, 1989, p.xxxii).

22 The much-quoted, and by our investigations the most-quoted statement, by Robbins to support the notion that economics is a science of scarcity appears in a trade book for non-technical readers. “We have been turned out of Paradise. We have neither eternal life nor unlimited means of gratification. Everywhere we turn, if we choose one thing we must relinquish others which, in different circumstances, we would not wish to have relinquished. Scarcity of means to satisfy given ends is an almost ubiquitous condition of human behaviour. Here, then, is the unity of the subject of Economic Science, the forms assumed by human behaviour in disposing of scarce means.” (Robbins, 1932, p15). We have vainly searched for an entry on ‘scarcity’ in Seligman (1930), Sills (1968), Higgs (1926) and Smelser and Baltes, 2004. It makes a late appearance in reference books as the organizing principle of economic science after being so popularized in textbooks, including that reliable standard by Paul Samuelson, Economics, first published in 1948.

23 “Optimizing, a catch-all term for maximizing, minimizing … lies at the heart of economic analysis. … Indeed, optimizing subject to constraints has been considered by many as defining the essential nature of economics” (Lancaster, 1968, pp9–10). To make constrained optimization meaningful in everyday language, he invokes the quotation from Robbins.

24 When a technical meaning is imposed, ‘scarcity’ becomes ordinarily meaningless as evident in the entry on ‘scarcity’ in Eatwell, Milgate and Newman, 1988. “But the meaning of scarcity within marginalist theory of distribution is very peculiar: it concerns only the relative quantities of the factors employed in production. We may say that a factor is scarce when increasing quantities of it applied to a given quantity of the other gives rise to decreasing returns.” [emphasis in original].

25 “There are some commodities, the value of which is determined by their scarcity alone. No labour can increase the quantity of such goods, and therefore their value cannot be lowered by an increased supply. Some rare statues and pictures, scarce books and coins, wines of a peculiar quality, which can be made only from grapes grown on a particular soil, of which there is a very limited quantity, are all of this description. Their value is wholly independent of the quantity of labour originally necessary to produce them, and varies with the varying wealth and inclinations of those who are desirous to possess them.” (Ricardo, 1821, p2).

26 Study Plato’s The Statesman for a decisive account of two kinds of measurement – the one ‘arithmetic’ (corresponding to finiteness) and the other ‘geometric’ (corresponding to scarcity). The philosophical implications and practical consequences of the distinction between these kinds of measurement have been well drawn out by Rosen, 1985.

27 Many papers in this volume emphasize the relational nature of ‘scarcity’. See the excellent paper in this volume by Jasveen Jairath who recognizes the importance of having a different word for quantitative measures of a thing. Obviously, we propose ‘finiteness’, as Fred Luks does explicitly and Nicholas Xenos implicitly, both in this volume. Accordingly, the debates on whether water scarcity is a ‘social construction’ or a ‘natural phenomenon’ are as fruitless as is the one on the supposed distinction between ‘absolute scarcity’ and ‘relative scarcity’. See the article by Lyla Mehta in this volume on the continued prevalence of such debates.

28 Papers in this volume provide ample evidence of the extent to which the idea of a market in water to reduce effective demand and increase supply dominates contemporary thinking on the topic. For an illustrative example in the burgeoning literature on water scarcity, see Saleth and Dinar, 2001, pp119–32. That scarcity and abundance are endemically viewed through the economic prism of demand and supply is perhaps most convincingly laid out in Gleick, 2004. The report is based on the unquestioned acceptance that water is an economic resource. Consequently, all its solutions to the problem of water can be clubbed under attempts that either increase water supply or manage the demand for it. See also Mehta 2003 for a critique of this.

29 Even the most ‘obvious’ economic law of an inverse relation between price and quantity demanded becomes dubious by slightly shaking one of the foundational assumptions of mathematical economics. See Stiglitz, 1987, pp1–48. He shows that changing the assumption of costless information upsets much of the neoclassical applecart. It is a matter of elementary logic that assumptions known to be false cannot lead to correct conclusions, except by accident.

30 Consult Jean Robert (1994) for extensive historical and theoretical analyses of water built on the distinction between water understood as commons and misunderstood as economic resource. See Illich (1985) for a glimpse of the historical rupture in perception attending the transmutation of water into a techno-scientific economic resource. The cases and argument presented above are culled from Horowitz (1977), esp. Ch. 2. He emphasizes that “the evolving law of water rights had a greater impact than any other branch of law on the effort to adapt private law doctrines to the movement for economic growth.” (p34).


[a]References

Achterhuis, H. (1993) ‘Scarcity and sustainability’, in Global Ecology: A New Arena for Political

Conflict, Zed Books, Boston, MA

Arendt, H. (1958) The Human Condition, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

Bentham, (1823) Introduction to the Principles of Moral and Legislation, London

Burke, E. (1795) Thoughts and Details on Scarcity

Cannan, Edwin. (1904). Introduction to An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of

Nations, by Adam Smith, 5th edition.

Dalton, G. (ed) (1968) Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies, Anchor Books, NY

Dumouchel, P. and J.-P. Dupuy, (1979) L’Enfer Des Choses, Seuil, Paris

Dumont, L. (1977) From Mandeville to Marx, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

Eatwell, Milgate and Newman (eds) (1988) New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, Macmillan,

NY

Edgeworth, F. (1926) Dictionary of Political Economy, Macmillan, London

Farmer, M. (1992) ‘Ever since Adam Smith: The mythical history of individual rationality in

economic analysis’, Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology, vol 9,

pp105–27

Finley, M. I. (1985) The Ancient Economy, University of California Press, Berkeley, CA

Foucault, M. (1998) ‘On governmentality’, in Gordon, C., Burchell, G. and Miller, P. (eds) The

Foucault Effect, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

Georgescu-Roegen, (ed) (1968) ‘Utility’, International Encyclopedia of Social Science, David

Sills, Free Press, NY

Girard, (1976) Deceit, Desire and the Novel, John Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD

Gleick, P. (ed) (2004) The World’s Water: The Biennial Report on Freshwater Resources, Island

Press, Washington, D.C.

Halévy, E. (1955) The Growth of Philosophical Radicalism, Beacon Press, Boston, MA

Henderson, J. and Quandt, R. (1988) Microeconomic Theory: A Mathematical Approach,

McGraw Hill, NY

Higgs, H. (ed) (1926) The Dictionary of Political Economy, Macmillan, NY

Hirschman, A. O. (1977) The Passions and the Interests, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

Hirshleifer, J. (1985) ‘The expanding domain of economics’, American Economic Review, 75, p53

Horowitz, M. (1977) The Transformation of American Law, 1780–1860, Harvard University

Press, Cambridge, MA

Howey, R. (1989) The Rise of the Marginal Utility School, Columbia University Press, NY

Illich, I. (1972) Tools of Conviviality, Marion Boyars, London

Illich, I. (1980) ‘The war on subsistence’, and ‘Vernacular values’ both in Shadow Work, Marion

Boyars, London

Illich, I. (1985) H2O and the Waters of Forgetfulness, Haydey Books, Berkeley, CA

James, S. (1999) Seeing Like a State, Yale University, Princeton, NJ

Jevons, (1988) (3rd ed) The Theory of Political Economy, Macmillan, London

Jolink, A. (1996) The Evolutionist Economics of Léon Walras, Routledge, NY

Kauder, E. (1953) ‘Genesis of the marginal utility theory from Aristotle to the end of the XVIIIth

century’, The Economic Journal, 63, pp638–50

Keynes, J. M. (1972) ‘Economic considerations for our grandchildren’, in Essays in Persuasion,

Collected Works, v.IX, Macmillan, NY

Lancaster, K. (1968) Mathematical Economics, Dover, NY

Le Goff, J. (1988) Medieval Civilization, 400–1500, Blackwell, London

Leiss, W. (1988) The Limits to Satisfaction, McGill University Press, Kingston

Letwin, W. (1963) Origins of Scientific Economics, London, pp147–8

Locke, J. Concerning Civil Government, second Essay, Ch.5

Lowry, S. T. (1987) The Archaeology of Economic Ideas, Durham

MacIntyre, A. (1984) After Virtue, Notre Dame University Press

Macpherson, C. B. (1962) The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke,

Oxford University Press, Oxford

Malthus, T. (1798) Essay on the Principle of Population

Mandeville, (1924) The Fable of the Bees, or private vices, publick benefits. Oxford University

Press, Oxford.

Marcos, Subcomandante Insurgente (2001) Our Word is our Weapon, Seven Stories Press, NY

Marshall, A. (1890) Principles of Economics, Macmillan, London

Marshall, A. (1898) (4th ed) Principles of Economics, London

Marx, K. (1954) Capital, vol.1, Progress Publishers, Moscow

Meikle, S. (1995) Aristotle’s Economic Thought, Clarendon Press, Oxford

Mirowski, P. (1988) ‘Physics and the “Marginalist Revolution”’, in Against Mechanism:

Protecting Economics from Science, Rowman & Littlefield, NY

Mirowski, P. (1989) More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics; Physics as Nature’s

Economy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Montes, L. (2003) ‘Das Adam Smith Problem: its origins, the states of the current debate, and one

implication for our understanding of sympathy’, Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 25,

pp63–90

Pearce, D. (ed) (1986) The MIT Dictionary of Economics, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

Poerksen, U. (1988) Plastic Words: The Tyranny of a Modular Language, Penn State Press, State

College, PA

Polanyi, K. (1944) The Great Transformation, Reinhart, NY

Polanyi, K., Arensberg, C. and Pearson, H. (eds) (1957) Trade and Markets in Early Empires, The

Free Press, NY

Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

Ricardo, D. (1821) (3rd ed) On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation

Robert, J. (1994) Water is a Commons, Habitat International Coalition, Mexico City

Robertson and Taylor (1957) ‘Adam Smith’s approach to the theory of Value’, The Economic

Journal, 67, pp181–98

Robbins, L. (1932) The Nature and Significance of Economic Science, Macmillan, London

Rosen, S. (1985) The Limits of Analysis, Yale University Press, CT

Sachs, W. (ed) (1992) The Development Dictionary, Zed Books, Boston, MA

Sahlins, M. (1972) Stone Age Economics, Adline, NY

Saleth, M. and Dinar, A. (2001) ‘Preconditions for market solutions to urban water scarcity:

empirical research from Hyderabad City, India’, Water Resources Journal, vol 37, pp119–32

Seligman, E. R. A. (ed) (1930) Encyclopaedia of Social Sciences, NY

Shanin, T. (1977) The Awkward Class, Cambridge, London

Sills, D. (ed) (1968) The International Encyclopaedia of Social Sciences, The Free Press, NY

Simon, H. (1991) ‘Organizations and markets’, Journal of Economic Perspective, 5, pp 25–44

Smelser, N. and Baltes, P. (eds) (2004) International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral

Sciences, Elsevier, NY

Smith, A. (1858) The Theory of Moral Sentiments

Smith, A. (1875) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations

Solow, R. (2006) ‘How to understand the economy,’ New York Review of Books, vol 53, pp.43–6

Steuart Denham, J. (1767) .An Inquiry into the Principles of Political Economy

Stigler, G. (1950) ‘Development of Utility Theory II’, Journal of Political Economy, 58, p373

Stiglitz, J. (1987) ‘The causes and consequences of the dependence of quality on price’, Journal of

Economic Literature, 1(1), pp1–48

Strauss, L. (1950) Natural Right and History, Chicago University Press, Chicago, IL

Thompson, E. P. (2000) ‘The moral economy of the crowd’, in Thompson, D. (ed) The Essential

E.P. Thompson, The New Press, NY

Weber, M. (1958) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Macmillan, NY

White, M. (2002) ‘Doctoring Adam Smith: The fable of the Diamond and Water Paradox’, History

of Political Economy, 34, pp659–83

Wolf, E. (1969) The Peasant Wars of the XXth Century, Harper & Row, NY

Xenos, N. (1989) Scarcity and Modernity, Routledge, London